Coercion As Cure: A Critical History Of Psychiatry By Thomas Szasz

BAB's A List,Pseudoscience,Psychiatry

            

My guest today on Barely a Blog is Thomas S. Szasz, Professor of Psychiatry Emeritus at the State University of New York Upstate Medical University, in Syracuse, New York. He is the author of 31 books, among them the classic, The Myth of Mental Illness (1961; revised edition, New York: HarperCollins, 1974). He is widely recognized as the world’s foremost critic of psychiatric coercions and excuses. He maintains that just as we reject using theological claims about people’s religious states (heresy) as justification for according them special legal treatment, we ought to reject using psychiatric claims about people’s mental states (mental illness) as justification for according them special legal treatment.
Dr. Szasz has received many awards for his defense of individual liberty and responsibility threatened by this modern form of totalitarianism masquerading as medicine. A frequent and popular lecturer, he has addressed professional and lay groups, and has appeared on radio and television, in North, Central, and South America as well as in Australia, Europe, Japan, and South Africa. His books have been translated into every major and many less than major languages. His website is: http://www.szasz.com/. The following is an edited (eponymous) version of the preface to Dr. Szasz’s forthcoming book, exclusive to BAB.–ILANA

COERCION AS CURE: A CRITICAL HISTORY OF PSYCHIATRY

By Thomas Szasz
All modern history, as learnt and taught and accepted, is purely conventional. For sufficient reasons, all persons in authority combined, by a happy union of deceit and concealment, to promote falsehood.
Lord Acton

For more than a century, leading psychiatrists have maintained that psychiatry is hard to define because its scope is so broad. In 1886, Emil Kraepelin, considered the greatest psychiatrist of his age, declared: “Our science has not arrived at a consensus on even its most fundamental principles, let alone on appropriate ends or even on the means to those ends.”
Contrary to such assertions, I maintain that it is easy to define psychiatry. The problem is that defining it truthfully — acknowledging its self-evident ends and the means used to achieve them — is socially unacceptable and professionally suicidal. Psychiatric tradition, social expectation, and the law — both criminal and civil — identify coercion as the profession’s determining characteristic. Accordingly, I regard psychiatry as the theory and practice of coercion, rationalized as the diagnosis of mental illness and justified as medical treatment aimed at protecting the patient from himself and society from the patient. The history of psychiatry I present thus resembles, say, a critical history of missionary Christianity.
The heathen savage does not suffer from lack of insight into the divinity of Jesus, does not lack theological help, and does not seek the services of missionaries. Just so, the psychotic does not suffer from lack of insight into being mentally ill, does not lack psychiatric treatment, and does not seek the services of psychiatrists. This is why the missionary tends to have contempt for the heathen, why the psychiatrist tends to have contempt for the psychotic, and why both conceal their true sentiments behind a facade of caring and compassion. Each meddler believes that he is in possession of the “truth,” each harbors a passionate desire to improve the Other, each feels a deep sense of entitlement to intrude into the life of the Other, and each bitterly resents those who dismiss his precious insights and benevolent interventions as worthless and harmful.
Non-acknowledgment of the fact that coercion is a characteristic and potentially ever-present element of so-called psychiatric treatments is intrinsic to the standard dictionary definitions of psychiatry. The Unabridged Webster’s defines psychiatry as “A branch of medicine that deals with the science and practice of treating mental, emotional, and behavioral disorders.”
Plainly, voluntary psychiatric relations differ from involuntary psychiatric interventions the same way as, say, sexual relations between consenting adults differ from the sexual assaults we call “rape.” Sometimes, to be sure, psychiatrists deal with voluntary patients. As I explain and illustrate throughout this volume, it is necessary, however, not merely to distinguish between coerced and consensual psychiatric relations, but to contrast them. The term “psychiatry” ought to be applied to one or the other, but not both. As long as psychiatrists and society refuse to recognize this, there can be no real psychiatric historiography.
The writings of historians, physicians, journalists, and others addressing the history of psychiatry rest on three erroneous premises: that so-called mental diseases exist, that they are diseases of the brain, and that the incarceration of “dangerous” mental patients is medically rational and morally just. The problems so created are then compounded by failure — purposeful or inadvertent — to distinguish between two radically different kinds of psychiatric practices, consensual and coerced, voluntarily sought and forcibly imposed.
In free societies, ordinary social relations between adults are consensual. Such relations — in business, medicine, religion, and psychiatry — pose no special legal or political problems. By contrast, coercive relations — one person authorized by the state to forcibly compel another person to do or abstain from actions of his choice — are inherently political in nature and are always morally problematic.
Mental disease is fictitious disease. Psychiatric diagnosis is disguised disdain. Psychiatric treatment is coercion concealed as care, typically carried out in prisons called “hospitals.” Formerly, the social function of psychiatry was more apparent than it is now. The asylum inmate was incarcerated against his will. Insanity was synonymous with unfitness for liberty. Toward the end of the nineteenth century, a new type of psychiatric relationship entered the medical scene: persons experiencing so-called “nervous symptoms” began to seek medical help, typically from the family physician or a specialist in “nervous disorders.” This led psychiatrists to distinguish between two kinds of mental diseases, neuroses and psychoses: Persons who complained of their own behavior were classified as neurotic, whereas persons about whose behavior others complained were classified as psychotic. The legal, medical, psychiatric, and social denial of this simple distinction and its far-reaching implications undergirds the house of cards that is modern psychiatry.
The American Psychiatric Association, founded in 1844, was first called the Association of Medical Superintendents of American Institutions for the Insane. In 1892, it was renamed the American Medico-Psychological Association, and in 1921, the American Psychiatric Association (APA). In its first official resolution, the Association declared: “Resolved, that it is the unanimous sense of this convention that the attempt to abandon entirely the use of all means of personal restraint is not sanctioned by the true interests of the insane.” The APA has never rejected its commitment to the twin claims that insanity is a medical illness and that coercion is care and cure. In 2005, Steven S. Sharfstein, president of the APA, reiterated his and his profession’s commitment to coercion. Lamenting “our [the psychiatrists’] reluctance to use caring, coercive approaches,” he declared: ” A person suffering from paranoid schizophrenia with a history of multiple rehospitalizations for dangerousness and a reluctance to abide by outpatient treatment, including medications, is a perfect example of someone who would benefit from these [forcibly imposed] approaches. We must balance individual rights and freedom with policies aimed at caring coercion.” Seven months later, Sharfstein conveniently forgot having recently bracketed caring and coercion into a single act, “caring coercion.” Defending “assisted treatment”–a euphemism for psychiatric coercion– he stated: “In assisted treatment, such as Kendra’s Law in New York, psychiatrists’ primary role is to foster patient improvement and help restore the patient to health.”

Psychiatry and society face a paradox. The more progress scientific psychiatry is said to make, the more intolerable becomes the idea that mental illness is a myth and that the effort to treat it a will-o’-the-wisp. The more progress scientific medicine actually makes, the more undeniable it becomes that “chemical imbalances” and “hard wiring” are fashionable clichés, not evidence that problems in living are medical diseases justifiably “treated” without patient consent. And the more often psychiatrists play the roles of juries, judges, and prison guards, the more uncomfortable they feel about being in fact pseudomedical coercers — society’s well-paid patsies. The whole conundrum is too horrible to face. Better to continue calling unwanted behaviors “diseases” and disturbing persons “sick,” and compel them to submit to psychiatric “care.” It is easy to see, then, why the right-thinking person considers it inconceivable that there might be no such thing as mental health or mental illness. Where would that leave the history of psychiatry portrayed as the drama of heroic physicians combating horrible diseases?
Alexander Solzhenitsyn is right: “Violence can only be concealed by a lie, and the lie can only be maintained by violence. Any man who has once proclaimed violence as his method is inevitably forced to take the lie as his principle.”
Scientific discourse is predicated on intellectual honesty. Psychiatric discourse rests on intellectual dishonesty. The psychiatrist’s basic social mandate is the coercive-paternalistic protection of the mental patient from himself and the public from the mental patient. Yet, in the professional literature as well as the popular media, this is the least noted feature of psychiatry as a medical specialty. Pointing it out is considered to be in bad taste. It would be difficult to exaggerate the extent to which historians of psychiatry as well as mental health professionals and journalists ignore, deny, and rationalize the involuntary, coerced, forcibly imposed nature of psychiatric treatments. This denial is rooted in language. Psychiatrists, lawyers, journalists, and medical ethicists routinely call incarceration in a psychiatric prison “hospitalization,” and torture forcibly imposed on the inmate “treatment.” Resting their reasoning on the same faulty premises, psychiatric historians trace alleged advances in the diagnosis and treatment of mental illnesses to “progress in neuroscience.” In contrast, I focus on what psychiatrists have done to persons who have rejected their “help” and on how they have rationalized their “therapeutic” violations of the dignity and liberty of their ostensible beneficiaries.
I regard consensual human relations, however misguided by either or both parties, as radically different, morally as well as politically, from human relations in which one party, empowered by the state, deprives another of liberty. The history of medicine, no less than the history of psychiatry, abounds in interventions by physicians that have harmed rather than helped their patients. Bloodletting is the most obvious example. Nevertheless, physicians have, at least until now, abstained from using state-sanctioned force to systematically impose injurious treatments on medically ill people. Misguided by fashion and lack of knowledge, sick people have often sought and willingly submitted to such interventions. In contrast, the history of psychiatry is, au fond, the story of the forcible imposition of injurious “medical” interventions on persons called “mental patients.”
In short, where psychiatric historians see stories about terrible illnesses and heroic treatments, I see stories about people marching to the beats of different drummers or perhaps failing to march at all, and terrible injustices committed against them, rationalized by hollow “therapeutic” justifications. Faced with vexing personal problems, the “truth” people crave is a simple, fashionable falsehood. That is an important, albeit bitter, lesson the history of psychiatry teaches us.
One of the melancholy truths of the story I have set out to tell is that, stripped of its pseudomedical ornamentation, it is not a particularly interesting tale. To make it interesting, I have tried to do what, according to Walt Whitman (1819-1892), the “greatest poet “does: He “drags the dead out of their coffins and stands them again on their feet…. He says to the past, Rise and walk before me that I may realize you.” To this end, I have, where possible, cited the exact words psychiatrists have used to justify their stubborn insistence, over a period of nearly three centuries, that psychiatric coercion is medical care.

13 thoughts on “Coercion As Cure: A Critical History Of Psychiatry By Thomas Szasz

  1. James Paty

    Wow! How incisive. I’ve never had contact with psychiatrists, thank God, and now I know why that’s a good thing. In your intro you made a point that has always bothered me about our justice system: that mental illness relieves a criminal of responsibility. Like the Muslim who killed the woman in Seattle(?) and shot several others. Instead of hanging him in an expeditious manner, he will get drugs and food and shelter until he is “fit” to return to society. I don’t want him in society. Nor Sirhan Sirhan.

  2. John Danforth

    Mr. Szasz zeroes in on the essential truth that made “One Flew Over The Cuckoo’s Nest” such a compellingly great book. Of course, the brilliantly cast movie made from it is a masterpiece.

    What he says needs to be said, even in polite company.

    Perhaps we could prescribe trepanation for those in the profession who advocate coercion. It is said to reduce violent tendencies.

    –John Danforth–

  3. Rick

    What a wonderful article and an eye opener for society at large. The injustice system in our country uses it for just about everything there is. It’s basically another “tool” to extort more money from the unsuspecting public. You go through a stop sign? The judge will send you to therapy. Getting divorced? We (the system) have the cure: Therapy. You want to see your own children? You need a psychological evaluation to the tune of thousands of dollars to see your own flesh and blood. You happen to be a real man? Well, you need “sensitivity training” and long-term therapy.

    Many thanks to professor Szasz for reaffirming my long time belief that this is nothing but hogwash.

  4. Phineas Worthington

    This explains the ‘psychiatric treatment’ sought by Mel Gibson and Mike Richards for their anti-semetic and racist rants. It’s not their fault, they’re just temporarily crazed.

    Despite their poor behavior, the equivocation of words with deeds is an error.

    Interesting how modern psychology equates words with deeds yet still manages to negate individual responsibility for both.

  5. Rick

    Where is my prior comment? Mrs. Mercer, I have enjoyed your column for the past couple years. Sadly, every time I give my humble opinion on any subject, it is not posted. If you have any reason for not doing so, please inform me and I will immediately cease to opine.

    [Hey, don’t I get to take a break on the New Year? Patience, people. I don’t have a web manger; it’s me who does all editing, posting, and updating (in addition to writing for assorted deadlines, and a lot of cooking, cleaning, ironing, and jogging, of course). That’s why it often takes a while for letters to appear. Rick, I believe your letters are strewn all over BAB.]

  6. Phineas Worthington

    Ilana, your efforts, though unseen, are greatly appreciated by this reader who also has no free time.

    I’d like to offer two examples of coerced psychotherapy and see if they fit the thesis proposed by Szasz in BAB.

    First, if a schizophrenic is a threat to himself or others, would it not fit the concept of natural law justice to lock him up? Not for his own good mind you, but for the safety of others. Locking him up simply for his own good would fit the perverted model of coercive thereapy written about by the Professor. Locking him up to preserve his own life from himself maybe more of a grey area. However, locking him up to remove the threat to the lives of others would seem to fit the concept of justice in natural law, yes?

    My second example is one experienced by someone with whom I am well acquainted. He was locked up in a mental hospital for a year for the crime of selling drugs as a minor. I think this might fit the criterion of coercive therapy that subverts the principles of natural law. To say nothing of the curious fact that the mental hospital was trying to force this person to take psychological drugs while being incarcerated for the use and selling of drugs. It seems at least an unfit punishment for the crime, especially since he had no mental illness. He certanily suffered emotional problems after his incarceration however.

  7. D. Saul Weiner

    Bravo to Dr. Szasz for his relentless attack against psychiatric coercion.

    My only quibble in this article is that he seems to say that there is an absence of coercion in the rest of medicine. When you think about the immunization program, fluoridated municipal water supplies, and court decisions mandating chemotherapy for minors who would elect otherwise, it is apparent that coercion is not confined to psychiatry.

  8. Rick

    Sorry about my impatience. Have you and yours a wonderful and happy New Year.

  9. dr.Laszlo Lajtavari

    Thomas Szasz immigrated to the US in 1938, when he was 18 years old, from Hungary. His father was a very clever man, who exactly felt the real danger that frightened the life of all Jews in Europe. Thomasz Szasz inherited his father’s “clearvoyance” ability. I’m a 59 year old hungarian psychiatrist who very much admires Szasz. He is right, and his ideas about psychiatry are as obvious today as they were when he wrote his famous book, “The myths of mental Illness”. In my country “mainstream” psychiatry thinks he is a heretic and only two of his books were edited in his mother tounge some years ago.
    I’m looking forward to reading his new book.

  10. Ilana Mercer Post author

    Dr. Thomas Szasz replies:

    In his comment of January 1, Mr. Worthington rightly emphasizes the distinction between words and deeds. Words — utterances before witnesses, letters or other published documents — are, to be sure, a species of action and may or may not be punishable by criminal sanctions. On January 2, Mr. Worthington asks, rhetorically: “… if a schizophrenic is a threat to himself or others, would it not fit the concept of natural law justice to lock him up?” My answer, of course, is that such a “diagnosis” would not justify locking up the subject under psychiatric auspices (because no one ought to be deprived of liberty under psychiatric auspices). If people and their legislators decide to make such “threats” punishable by criminal sanctions, and if a person is convicted under such a law, then it may be said to be “justifiable” to lock him up under the auspices of the criminal justice system. In that case, we would have added one more very bad law to our criminal laws.
    I leave it to the readers to ponder why we moderns are predisposed — as Mr. Worthington’s second comment implies — to assume that persons called “schizophrenic” ought to have less rights (and responsibilities) than “non-schizophrenic” persons.

    –Thomas Szasz

  11. Phineas Worthington

    Thank you, Dr. Szasz, for your kind response.

    May I address the following:
    Mr. Worthington’s second comment implies — to assume that persons called “schizophrenic” ought to have less rights (and responsibilities) than “non-schizophrenic” persons.

    I was going on the assumption that schizophrenics have equal rights to people of sound mind. As such, any threats of force schizophrenics may make against others are a violation against the rights of the innocents. Hence, it seems proper for the law to punish for such violations. “Crazy” people need to be held accountable for their actions just like people of sound mind.

    It seems proper for law to punish threats of force, even the threats of schizophrenics.

    I know, for instance, that for the average man, it only takes an accusation of a threat to get a restraining order against him. That, in turn, can lead to the taking away of second amendment rights and other rights too.

    I am indeed trying to make my argument on the basis of an objective concept of equality.

  12. Sam

    It is sad, but true. Thomas Szasz line of thought rings out even more now in the 21st Century. However, there are schools in which psychology, and psychiatry, are taught as an art–in essence, one human being making a sincere effort to understand another’s lived experience. Yet in the day and age of managed care, the established consensus discounts this approach as sheer quackery. The way I was taught Thomas Szasz, the self-proclaimed experts need to perpetuate a faulty perspective in order to collect a pay check, and maintain a position of unquestioned authority.

  13. Laura Borst

    Dr. Szasz made some very true comments regarding the history of psychiatry. These comments are all too relevant in the present. There is no objective physical test for any “mental illness”,although psychiatrists claim there are such tests. However, the magnetic resonance imaging scans that are claimed to be indicative of “schizophrenia” really illustrate the brain damage that neuroleptic, also called “antipsychotic”, drugs can cause. Very often, people who claim to “help” people often harm them.

Comments are closed.